― tarden, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
Without the concept of personal taste and discrimination, what the hell is there to stop the individual from drowning in a fucking sea of overwhelming, often contradictory information? Are we data processing machines? No, we are humans. Vive la Taste, De Gustibus Non Disputandum Est. (sorry, high school Latin a bit rusty)
― masonic boom, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― MJ Hibbett, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― the pinefox, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― -- Mike Hanley, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
"...no, everyone does NOT have the right to an opinion. Everyone has the right to an INFORMED opinion."
One can either say that some opinions have more value than others, or that all opinions have the same value. The latter would be considered ludicrous in science or literary criticism; why is it acceptable in the arts? To my way of thinking, it shouldn't be, and yet there are a lot of people who seem to think so.
The notion that "everything is relative" in music or art is part of the ongoing devaluation of the arts, which has been well underway since the Romantic era. One of my old professors recently reminded me of a Hegel quote which I love -- something like "And thus are the constituent parts of the spiritual life of mankind reduced to the categories of mere entertainment and superstition." The arts and religion, respectively. And however you feel about it, there's no denying that the revelatory power of the arts has been marginalized, in favor of their role as entertainment (with an emphasis on novelty), by our growing cultural emphasis on the financial, the utilitarian, and instant gratification. (Yes, I know, we've all heard that phrase or variations on it countless times, and are sick of hearing about it -- but the problem is, it's true.)
In music, a lot of the responsibility for the acceleration of this devaluation may well lie squarely at the doorstep of John Cage. Treated rather cruelly at the hands of Schoenberg, he acquired a lifelong animosity towards the musical establishment, and his work eventually led him to break the contract that had always existed between composers and their audience -- the contract of intent: that the composer is trying to articulate something aesthetically meaningful through his music, and that it would be worthwhile for an audience to expend the effort to understand that something. While many lovely sounds came out of Cage's subsequent explorations and random processes, the significance of that contract-breaking cannot be underestimated. The balance of power had been permanently shifted, from the composer to his/her audience; no longer was it necessary to acknowledge the possibility that one's own ignorance was the culprit in a failure to understand a piece of music. Now, "everything was the same as everything else"; all sounds were considered equally meaningful; there was no good or bad, only how you choose to see it. Innocuous and inclusive as it may sound, this is arguably an unbelievably crushing outlook, since (to condense the relevant arguments tremendously) if you do away with both the ideas of a supernatural absolute (an afterlife, typically one in which people are brought to account for their actions), and any kind of secular absolute (the notion of aesthetic and ethical truth), then the only absolute remaining is death: in the arts, aesthetic death (meaninglessness), and in politics, mass murder (cf. The Reign of Terror, the Russian Revolution, et al.). Hegel and Nietzsche were certainly on to this, and their respective philosophies are, in part, responses to the prospect of this abyss.
For the record, unlike my professor, I like a fair amount of Cage's music. I think his alienation from the musical establishment (at first, anyway) led him to come up with some wild and interesting ideas, and the Sonatas and Interludes for prepared piano are beautiful. But I've had the misfortune to sit through other pieces of his which are absolutely dreadful and self-indulgent, and I'm slowly coming around to the viewpoint that quite a few of them are little more than expressions of contempt, as though Cage were laughing in the rafters at the establishment that once humiliated him, saying in essence, "I could shit on a plate and serve it up to you, and you'd still sit there and nod your heads." It's The Emperor's New Clothes all over again. Those pieces don't bring about open minds, they bring about closed minds, insulted and shellshocked at being subjected to "sound and fury, signifying nothing", and less likely to be receptive to challenging ideas in the future.
So no, I don't exactly hate it when people say they "just don't like" something. What I hate, rather, is the failure on a societal level to acknowledge that aesthetic truth and value are not purely relative, nor are they democratically determined (if they are, then Bach is the inferior of Telemann in his own time, and Britney Spears in ours). And I hate the idea that, in the interests of economics, the arts have shown more and more of a tendency to avoid, at all costs, confronting their audience with its own ignorance (since -- to take a rather oversimplified example -- if everything is the same as everything else, why bother to play good-but-challenging music when you can sell out, play crap, and make three times as much money? It's all relative, after all...).
The answer to all of this is not a totalitarian regime, as your pisstake jestingly suggests. Rather, it's in the rediscovery of intelligent and courageous criticism (part of which is the willingness to say, from an informed perspective, that certain things are shit -- John Cage's Water Music, aka "quack-a-duck-call-while-playing-a-radio-and-hitting-random-notes-on-the-piano" -- and certain things are beautiful -- his Sonatas and Interludes), and in the revaluation of the arts and their power to transport, to illuminate, and to enrich. While there's plenty of room for disagreement on what constitutes an informed opinion, it's the only viable basis for worthwhile criticism -- and the critique, or the power of critical thinking, is perhaps the most crucial element in our defense against every form of horror, be it aesthetic or political.
― Phil, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― DG, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
So anyway, who gets to decide what is musically worthy and what is mass murder ? I kind of see what you're trying to get at, and I don't entirely disagree with it, but there's something about it that makes me uncomfortable. Informed opinions are better, sure, but I don't think I'd go much beyond that - appreciation of music is kind of intangible.
― Patrick, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
The difference, as I see it, lies mainly in communication. One can have one's gut reactions and cherish them and never back down from them, and that's wonderful. But as soon as a person wants to talk to another person about music---as soon as two people with different subjective reactions want to discuss a piece of music and work out what value it has---that "taste"-based analysis becomes largely useless. It provides five seconds of conversation: "I like it." "I don't." Beyond that, it's analytical: "*Why* do you like it?"
Anyway. This issue seems to pop up quite often among "informed" music listeners, and I think it's key to maintain that the two elements of music appreciation are completely separate, and value judgements should not be attached to either. Value judgements should be attached to people who cannot distinguish between the two.
-- nta
― Nitsuh, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― mark s, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
I also think that an artist who "confronts the audience with its own ignorance" is making an awful lot of assumptions about his or her audience, assumptions that even those wearing the Emperor's Old Clothes weren't making. In fact, historically speaking, appreciation of the arts required a great deal of recognition of myths, symbols, motifs.
As far as Cage, I remember Brian Eno saying that Cage had the biggest influence on him even though he never listened to his records. For me, he's very similar to Duchamp.
― Kerry Keane, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― Mitch Lastnamewithheld, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
God, I wish I had the time to really keep up with these thought- provoking threads! I feel I'm growing a new prefrontal lobe just to keep track of them.
I like Cage, both the silences and the outbursts. As for Duchamp, I once even wrote a thesis on "The Bride Stripped Bare," for which Duchamp might even be said to have written a soundtrack. (I have it on record, but it's not exactly Mantovani.)
Oh, Lord, I have written too much today...
― X. Y. Zedd, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
This reminds me a parallel I meant to draw earlier, between music and two other endeavors in which subjective taste and objective value create some friction. The first, and more interesting, is the realm of the political, in which the same complaints can be made: that either (a) ill-informed, subjectively biased know-nothings exert too much of a voting influence over public policy, or (b) elitist bean- counters exert too much of an intellectual influence over public policy. While pretty much everyone can see the ways in which (a) is an unfortunate aspect of democracy, it has been generally decided by most of the world that some form of representative democracy is the only semi-fair way of making public policy decisions, even if it means that certain citizens will make irrational, ill-informed voting decisions that are the political equivalent of, say, listening to Phil Collins records.
The difference, of course, is that the state must make decisions, and those decisions must affect each of us. We should, perhaps, be really happy that democratic declarations of value in music---say, Phil Collins massive record sales in comparison to the Boredoms'---do not mean that Phil Collins gets to decide what sorts of records we will get to listen to for the next few years. The taste/value debate becomes something of a moot point---we can visit ILM and engaging in analytical/spectulative contemplation of pop music, and someone else can sit at home listening to "No Jacket Required," and while those decisions may strike one or the other as *annoying,* they're in no way *harmful* to anyone else involved.
The other comparison to be made, the more vexed and fraught one, is to the "canon wars" in literary criticism---a field in which approaches like "Reader Response Theory" that seem to favor intuitive "reaction" over objective "meaning" are rapidly chipping away at the traditional route through the canon. I won't even go into that, but I'd be interested to hear what others think. . .
― Josh, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
I did consider this, Josh, but I feel it's a bit of a moot point in terms of the comparison I was trying to make. My point was that in the political realm, *one* decision must be made in any given public policy quarrel. Either we reduce the top tax rate, or we don't. We're free to go on believing that that reduction is a bad idea, but those taxes will stay be paid at the lower rate.
This is only sort of the case with music. True, if J-Lo holds the number one Billboard spot (the presidency) and the Microphones only sell a couple hundred records (mayor of Olympia), the economics of the market are going to pull the entire music business in J-Lo's direction at the Microphones' expense. But that only corresponds to the fact that a political figure---president, prime minister---can pull a nation's agenda or public debate in his/her own direction. It doesn't quite correspond to the actual legislative power a political leader has; for that to be the case, J-Lo's #1 Billboard spot would have to entitle her to, say, decide what songs the Microphones could use on their album.
So I'd agree with what you're saying as far as it applies to the analogy of political *opinion*---that is, purely what people think or believe---but not in terms of my analogy to political *action*, in which one thing has to be decided on and all must abide by it.
But all of this is just a side-track from a whole other issue . . .
Arguably the "it's all gone downhill since the 18th century" sentiments are basically elegies for feudalism - as Adorno suggested (and it was one of his more sympathetic points re: music I'd say) the idea that music could gain autonomy post-feudalism through the ability to be bought and sold and yet not become dependent on market forces is a paradox that could exist in reality for only the briefiest period of time. True, Bach was not driven by market forces, but that's the luxury you have with a rigid, tightly-structured and pre-determined audience.
Phil's suggestion (and I'm paraphrasing obviously) seems to be that Cage brought about the death of the composer and thus the audience aquired a tyrannic role in the production of their own taste. Similar revelations in literature for example didn't provoke orgiastic responses of "I like it 'cos I like it, so there" in critical works, true, but that's because responses (Barthesian, deconstructionist etc.) still tended to rely on intelligent explication to get across the writer's often personal non-author-derived conclusions. It would be unfair to compare these to the inarticulate expression of appreciation of the average music listener who is obviously far closer to the average book reader - and if you went up to a Joan Collins reader on the beach, grabbed his or her book and started preaching about its worthlessness I would still applaud her right to punch you in the face and keep reading.
And anyway it's a myth that the 'people' ever had a keen appreciation of complex or avante garde artforms (and when I say 'myth' I do mean a cultural/ideological tool in the ongoing process of white male bourgeoisie ex-nomination). The prominence of popular culture has always existed, only in the form of unwritten songs, unrecorded events, unwritten opinions, because the producers and audiences were considered beneath critical evaluation.
The 'tyranny' of relativism is in my mind a direct result of the (perhaps still superficial) acceptance that no person's life is worth more than another's. J Lo's rich and the Microphones are poor, yes, but we don't need musical analogies to know that economic disadvantage is one of the more glaring discrepancies in our nominally equal society.
― Tim, Tuesday, 12 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
One thing I failed to articulate in my argument...was nicely said by Nitsuh. His distinction between "taste" and "aesthetic opinion" is something that I meant to include, or at least hint at -- but looking back at my initial post, I didn't, which could easily leave one with the impression, I think, that I was advocating a rather repressive outlook. I didn't mean to imply for one moment that there was no subjective element to music, quite the contrary -- when I said that they were "not purely relative" I meant precisely that -- in other words, that an objective component does exist (Tangentially, there seems to be some conflation happening of the relative and the subjective, which are two different things). Obviously music appreciation, and criticism, is a mixture of the subjective and the objective, as it is with any art; I'm certainly not so byzantine (nor foolish) as to suggest that it's purely objective. So Josh, yes, I certainly think that two informed individuals can form wholly different -- even diametrically opposed -- evaluations of a piece of music, and neither one is necessarily "incorrect" by any means. De Gustibus Non Disputandum Est, indeed -- and for that matter, intuitive reactions are part of the bread and butter of listening to, and loving, music, or any other art form. (We just have to be mindful of the premises upon which those intuitive reactions are based.)
Regarding Cage's "contempt" for the audience, I stand by my initial comment. I know that his writings, statements and even demeanor contradict it -- yet I still believe it's there in some of the music. I'm willing to concede that it's a highly subjective response, though.
Mitch said: "Isn't this what post-modernism is about?...The devaluation of the power of the author and the elevation of the importance of the audience's interpretation?" Hmmmmm. Frankly, I don't like the sound of that -- my first reaction is that it's anathema to my own aesthetic principles. If so, I guess I'm not a postmodernist, which hardly comes as a surprise. ;-) He also said, "If we reject notions of personal taste, then who shall we trust to produce a universal set of aesthetics for all to abide by?" Well, I haven't rejected the notion of personal taste, only the notion that it should reign supreme and function as the barometer of value. I certainly don't see having some sort of aesthetic Code of Hammurabi as valuable, nor was it something I intended to advocate. Off the top of my head, the only aesthetic absolute I'm willing to postulate is the same one for which I initially attacked Cage: I feel comfortable requiring intent. That doesn't mean microscopic control; algorithmic music can be perfectly viable, if you choose the right algorithms, and in general, any process can create something wonderful. As a composer at least, though, I see processes like those as a way of generating material, rather than as an end in and of itself. If the process happens to generate something worthwhile, that's great -- but I tend to think there's a correlation between the probability of worthwhile output, and the amount of control that one can trace back to the original algorithm (or premises of the process) -- in other words that one can tend to foresee at least part of the outcome of an algorithm or process that produces attractive results. I don't think the output of a fully random process tends to be interesting, no more than the other twenty billion books besides Hamlet produced by the monkeys chained to typewriters would tend to be interesting.
Kerry said: "I also think that an artist who 'confronts the audience with its own ignorance' is making an awful lot of assumptions about his or her audience, assumptions that even those wearing the Emperor's Old Clothes weren't making. In fact, historically speaking, appreciation of the arts required a great deal of recognition of myths, symbols, motifs." Well, music is not, and will never be, truly ahistorical, and there will always be a correlation between one's understanding of the signs and signifiers of a particular art form and one's ability to appreciate its subtleties. For instance, a Western musician, listening to certain types of Indian classical music and hearing a drone of C-F (with the F on top), would tend to assume that the F is the tonic and that the chord is inverted, since in Western music the fifth tends to be the normative sonority. However, as both observation and theory indicate, the C is often the tonic, and the fourth is treated as a viable normative interval. That's perhaps an overly theoretical example, but the point is that there will always be a differential in a listener's ability to appreciate any art, based on that person's understanding of innumerable factors, including its theory, its history, its social context, and so forth. I wrote more about this on my page a few weeks ago.
As for "confronting an audience with its own ignorance", I didn't intend to conjure the image of (for instance) some serialist composer, sternly lecturing the audience for being "ever so stupid". Rather, my point was simply that the commercialization of the arts consistently discourages artists from using a language that isn't instantly comprehensible and gratifying to the most uneducated, or inattentive, audience. When art is evaluated first and foremost by its ability to turn a profit, anything that would alienate any portion of the audience, even if it's something necessary to the aesthetic achievement of the work, is deprecated. Hence, the business-model of art avoids confronting people with, among other things, what they aren't equipped to understand, or aren't interested in putting any effort into appreciating. American orchestras don't play Schoenberg and Morton Feldman, because they believe that people don't understand those composers, or don't want to be challenged, even though their music is generally acknowledged to be of the highest order. So my intent wasn't to characterize audiences as ignorant, but rather to characterize the business-model as inherently catering to, and encouraging, ignorance, by deprecating the challenging in favor of the easily digested. And, yes, Britney Spears and Bach can co-exist, but if it were left to the mercy of the market, Bach would be dispensed with the moment he was no longer profitable. (Not that I pine for the system of patronage, either -- that had its own problems, to say the least.)
I certainly don't believe that "it's all gone downhill" since the 18th century, 19th century, or any particular point in time. It's true that, though there are areas in which history could be said to be at least partly teleological -- for instance, Western medicine and human rights -- I don't believe that, in the arts at least, subsequent developments have necessarily constituted "improvements" over what came before (so, for instance, Chopin isn't "better" than Mozart by dint of having access to a wider scope of accepted harmonic possibilities). That being said, though I do perceive a shift from the perception of art as revelatory and meaningful towards art as commercial entertainment, that in no way can be generalized to a belief on my part that the past 150 years (or whatever) have been a decline. That would, among many other things, neatly snip out 95% or more of my favorite music, including the entire genres of jazz, pop/rock, and electronic music, and most of the classical music I really love. The identification of a trend on my part does not sum up my beliefs about recent history as a whole, by any means!
Finally, I was roundly criticized off-list by a friend for conflating the political and the musical, and my muddled argumentation therein; the point is well taken, and I didn't intend to postulate aesthetic and ethical relativism as equivalencies.
So again, my purpose was not to deny the subjective and the personal -- only the notion that it should reign supreme. I mean, come on, I like Wesley Willis -- and while it's not inconceivable that I could defend him on aesthetic grounds, it'd be a largely silly idea. There's plenty of room in the world for taste (even bad taste!), and it need not always be grounded in argumentation or even rationality. I am almost wholly ignorant of the visual arts, and the fact that I like Mondrian and Kandinsky (for instance) is largely a function of intuitive affinity. I defend my right to have that affinity, but I don't claim that it's the product of any depth of understanding on my part, nor that it's equivalent to a deep critical examination. I do "just like it", but I acknowledge the fact that I lack the tools to articulate that liking, and that, knowing my ignorance, I should maintain an open mind as much as possible. (I don't need to feel guilty or inferior, just reasonably humble and receptive.) Thus, as a near-Philistine, when I am confronted with a painting which challenges me, or seems beyond my comprehension -- particularly a work that is said to be of value by people whose opinions I trust -- I know that I should strive to understand it, so long as I'm given grounds to believe that there was intelligent intent behind its creation.
Not to say Cage was always coherent or uncontradictory in his position: on one hand, he was a total control freak on the manner of performance. On the other, late in life (in the 80s), with the various mesostic operas, I think he got into a shtick-groove and wrote-performed as a habit of himself (ran out of devices to banish the seduction of pre-formed structure, summink like that).
Re Duchamp: well, Cage's works operate as mind-gags, so yes. But above all HE WANTED YOU TO HEAR THEM.
Phil, I can't tell from your description of Water Music if you just encountered a lousy performance, or you feel the composition is intrinsically dud. (Incidentally, to complain about self- indulgence AND lack of intent strikes me as bizarre...)
― mark s, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― Mitch Lastnamewithheld, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― tarden, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
You could say that every aleatory composer 'relinquishes creative control' in his own very distinctive -- and highly creative -- way. Eno's experiments with the Koan computer program still sound pretty Eno-like. Artistic intention is not so easily banished. Kick it out the front door and it comes in through the bathroom window.
As a practising musician, I'd also say that the choice of selling out and making three times as much money is not a realistic one. Personality is destiny. Again, the problem is escaping from Intent. People see through your shoddy motives. They see your discomfort, the fact that you're torn between integrity and the desire to be popular. The masses tend to buy records by artists without such conflicts: showbiz troopers like Robbie Williams, Elton John and Phil Collins. People whose personality profile matches 'actor' better than 'artist'. Who'd do and be anything to be popular.
I also resist the idea that where there are no objective standards, chaos, anarchy and 'horrors' inevitably ensue. It's like saying that only belief in God stops us all being murderers. You're forgetting empathy -- the same quality which makes us listen to the works of Cage, even when they're just the sound of a radio being tuned, and feel like he must have had something very profound to communicate. Empathy makes us construct artistic intent even where there is none. It makes the world go 'Bong! Pling! Parp!' It transforms the sound of paint pots and a transistor radio into 'The Fontana Mix'.
― Momus, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― matthew james, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
I think someone's subjectivity is getting the better of him. Schoenberg and Feldman are not "generally acknowledged to be of the highest order"---Schoenberg and Feldman are not even generally known to exist, relative to global culture's widespread recognition of Bach or Presley. The general acknowledgement you speak of exists only among the miniscule cadre who happen to (a) know a whole lot about music and (b) approach that music in an particularly analytical way--- or, I suppose, (c): people who take more pleasure from listening to Vivaldi, but are willing to stipulate that if people such as (a) and (b) say Feldman's brilliant, they probably have a point.
So I'm not sure I follow any of the carping about how economics affects aesthetic consumption. Music is enjoyed and consumed by a higher proportion of the world public than ever before, and most of them seem to really, really like what they're hearing. Perhaps many of them would enjoy being exposed to the types of music that music- lover cognoscenti would argue are "better"---but that's a bit like saying that everyone should be made to go skydiving, as they might end up liking it a whole lot. As it stands, most people don't really care about music, and as such we have a music industry that churns out *product* for people who don't really care about music.
That was the source of my political analogy. The U.S. public-policy debate, for instance, tends to cater to people who don't really follow or care about the details of politics---everything is painted in broad, vague phrases about "opportunity" or "dignity" that leave many with no clue about what public policy issues exist and how political candidates plan to approach them. This, I'd assert, is a case in which *it matters* that most people don't care (see my response to Josh above). But in terms of the music market, how do we justify arguments that it matters? To extend on the art analogy in previous posts: does the fact that I drink cheap wine, or know very little about modern sculpture, constitute an intellectually unjustifiable lowering of standards in those particular fields?
Thus I'm in complete agreement with the art analogy, and have tried to formulate the same argument in similar debates in the past. The key is being able to mentally differentiate between the two sorts of "liking"---and to be able to admit, for instance, that if the only poem you've ever read in your life is by Robert Frost, perhaps your negative reaction to Hart Crane shouldn't carry much weight.
That said, I *do* think we'd be better off with an intellectual / aesthetic culture in which people sort of desired to or took pleasure in experiencing those things that are considered refined tastes. We seem to reject a whole lot of activities since they're seen as remnants of cultural elitism, class stratification, "snootiness," etc.---but my take has always been that wealthy, educated elites, who have access to just about any experience culture can offer, tend largely to choose those experiences that are, in the end, pretty good. Which is to say: to reject a cultural experience because it's the province of the elite is sort of like rejecting a million dollars because it's the province of the wealthy.
― Nitsuh, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
>>> Music is enjoyed and consumed by a higher proportion of the world public than ever before, and most of them seem to really, really like what they're hearing.
Well - many people like a lot of what they hear. But most of us also dislike - even hate - a lot of what we hear. Maybe that wasn't meant to be included in your account. I just think that a full account of 'the experience of music today' (let alone at some other time) would have to include a lot of negativity as well as all that positivity you mention.
― the pinefox, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
Answer: They don't. I mean, honestly. I will give you everything I own if you can get more than two members of Celine Dion's fan club to buy more than one Morton Feldman recording.
― X. Y. Zedd, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
It seems to me that there are two different bits of processing going on, and they can happen in either order, or at once. One is deciding whether you like something. This is almost entirely subjective, and primarily a visceral decision for most people, although it can be encumbered with as much other stuff as you can convince your synapses to tolerate, and of course you can change your mind over time. The other is deciding what artistic virtues and flaws you think it has, which is also often subjective, but sometimes by being really painstaking about defining terms and calibrating mutual reference points you can get to agreements that are close enough to objective for practical purposes.
The bulk of popular-music listeners, who only ask for music to be entertainment, not art, have no reason to care about the second point, and while it's arguably a significant loss in their lives, and the root cause of the overwhelming awfulness of most commercial music, even by superficial standards, you're probably not going to get anywhere trying to badger them into subjecting the music they think they like to criteria that don't matter to them. If you want to communicate with people who only care whether they like something or not, you have to somehow shift at least part of your argument into their defined sphere. The most promising opening, I think, is that even people who don't analyze or understand music at all are bound to resent the inevitable effects of their ignorance. They'll buy the album for the song they think they like, and hate the rest of it. Or they'll like it now, but they'll get sick of it in two weeks. This is the only operable definition of "bad taste" I've been able to come up with, in fact, the inability to extrapolate in any direction from your own responses. If you can convince them examining the music and their reactions to it a little more closely will tangibly reduce the frustration and disappointment in their lives, they might give you a chance.
But most music-geeks learn very quickly not to try to talk theory with commoners, especially not if you have to explain Duchamp and Cage before you can discuss them, thus these forums. I agree that Cage's efforts to eliminate intent from music (his own description, whether you think he succeeded or not) were profoundly wrongheaded and destructive, in much the same way that moral relativism makes trouble for ethics education. But we must confront these things. "4:33" should be in any serious art curriculum, even if it's our fondest hope that not a single person who sits through a performance of it rushes home to become a conceptual artist themselves. It isolates some crucial bits of truth about how we make and label "art", plus it's a lot shorter and easier to stage than the Ring Cycle.
The problem with trying to only judge art on artistic merit, removing all subjectivity from the process, is that without some personal value judgments, even the semi-objective things are virtually impossible to weigh against each other. We might be able to agree that a certain song's lyrics are poetically inventive, and that the music to which they are set is banal, but then what? Do good lyrics beat out ordinary music, or vice versa? It seems to me that the most valuable discussions have to account for both dimensions of analysis. What are we doing if not trying to help each other find more rewarding ways to relate to music? Conducting dissing contests, most likely, which is juvenile. This is why all those polarizing classic/dud/search/destroy formula threads are a waste of time, whether the voters back up "i like it" with "just because" or elaborate theories. Tallying up the yeses and nos doesn't improve anybody's life. Turning somebody's no into a yes, however, might. Even turning a yes into a no, if it establishes a context for turning some other nos into yeses, might be valuable. Reducing music to the quantifiability of structural engineering would only leave us in exactly the quandary engineering faces: building the bridge is easy; the hard parts are deciding which rivers to cross, and keeping the people on either side from beating the crap out of each other the moment they no longer have to risk drowning to do so.
― glenn mcdonald, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― Mitch Lastnamewithhel, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
The story about his wanting revenge on Schoenberg is garbage, as well. As is the idea that Schoenberg was "the establishment" when Cage was his pupil: hard offhand to think of someone LESS the establishment at that particular time.
And that is why I think Glenn is the most brilliant person alive.
Seriously: this is the neatest little intellectual turn-around I have ever seen. The argument usually runs that the concept of "bad taste" is defined by aesthetic elites, and as such is forced upon common people who have absolutely no need of it. That argument is sometimes true and sometimes not, which makes it very hard to justify the "bad taste" concept in those instances where it really does *not* seem to be rooted in elitism. Glenn's argument completely bats that problem aside by providing what I'd never thought possible: a utiliarian advantage to what's normatively known as "good taste."
Of course, those with bad taste have a loophole: they can just ask friends with slightly better taste to recommend records. The aesthetic elite, in a sense, does all of the classification legwork for everyone else, which is as close to the root purpose of a traditional music critic as I can think of: they tell the public what the public would probably like best.
Not that it always turns out that way, but. . .
I definitely think this capacity is laudable and desirable, but it's not 'good taste', nor is the lack of it bad taste. It's something else.
As for the 'dissing contests,' I think Glenn's right that a lot of the C/D / S/D etc. threads here get a little numbing. But that's because they're overdone, and done not all that well, often. Knowing whether a lot of the people here like something (or don't!), and a bit on why, is helpful within the context of our knowing things about one another. I'm not really partial to glammy-type music, so if for example Ned speaks kindly of someone and talks about the apparent Bowie influence in their music, it helps me know that I might want to put that band on the back burner on my mental check-this-out list. Or similarly, if it sounds like something I might like, for other reasons, but Ned also says it's glammy, I might see that as my opportunity to find ways to explore glammy music in general. Likewise for shedding additional light on music that I already like, or don't when I've heard it. Those 'waste of time' threads have the potential to change nos into yeses, etc.
I have more to say I guess but I'm trying to take it bit by bit.
― Josh, Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
I also dislike when people try to dismiss theories like cultural relativism out of hand because it 'doesn't work'. If the argument holds logically, then we must deal with the consequences. Otherwise, we look like the crazy farmer, pouring the milk into the bucket with the hole in it and saying "what are you staring at?"
― Dave M., Wednesday, 13 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
As for "4:33" being or not being "conceptual art", I didn't mean that to be a controversial idea either. It's the most prominent work of conceptual art most people know of. If we can't agree on a definition that simple, then little wonder we have such a hard time agreeing on anything subtler. And yes, in part it's about listening, but it is also a work of art that applies the label "art" to something that is not normally considered such (as do Duchamp's readymades), which means it's also very much about how we define art. This too seems like a very simple and uncontroversial assertion.
As for Josh's good point about "good taste", I think it's possible that "taste" is such a muddled concept that "good taste" and "bad taste" are not opposites. I don't have a working definition of "good taste". Pretty much the only usage of it that I feel like I understand is when it's said of interior decorators, in which case it almost always means the ability to look at objects or materials in one context (a store, a catalog) and predict how they're going to look in another context (the target room). When it's used about music, it invariably means that the person who has the taste mostly likes the same bands as the person praising it.
― glenn mcdonald, Thursday, 14 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
Apologies for possible muddle above, tired and entering this with a browser such that I only get to see 30 characters of a line at a time which is murder for someone with long sentences like me.
― Josh, Thursday, 14 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
I just felt he was being treated as the pathological extreme case, this irresponsible pomo clown who destroyed everything which Good and Decent. Based on an academic "version~ of his aesthetic which had little or no sanction in his actual work.
Not that he isn't an intensely complex, contradictory figure: but of course THAT'S what that should be studied, not what bogue academic art "historians" think is his "contribution".
Re: Conceptual Art. Isn't the "problem" (or indeed the glory) with CA that it's ALL intent and no content?
― mark s, Thursday, 14 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
Exercise to mull over: make a list of who you think has 'good taste' and 'bad taste' (in general - say, "teenyboppers" or "classical bores" or whatever - and specific, say "my uncle Fred"). Try to do it without thinking too hard - just think of a person, say "does it sound right to say 'X has good taste in music'?" - also then analyze your list and see if you agree with your choices, and try to explain to yourself why you made them. I've been playing this game at home tonight and it's very, very revealing.
Two people stand in front of two canvases, both of which are painted entirely back. Person A says, "These are identical black canvases, and I don't them." Person B says, "I don't like them either, but they're not identical: you can see that the patina on this one is completely different."
It mainly seems like an ability to compartmentalize and distinguish between *elements* of a particular work. Most gut-reaction listeners form opinions in a very Gestalt fashion---either it works or it doesn't. This new Glenn-derived definition of "taste" explains how some listeners can listen to a Phil Collins track and say, "Well of course, this sucks, but I must admit the production on that left- channel percussion track is just spectacular."
― Nitsuh, Thursday, 14 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
― Josh, Friday, 15 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link
1. He doesn't do a very good job, I think, differentiating between the analytical process of recognizing the individual virtues and flaws of a work and the judgmental process of weighing them against each other. He declares that failings of the organs may affect a person's ability to recognize the characteristics of a work, which seems reasonable enough, but then, after going through a long list of reasons why one person's opinion about those characteristics could differ radically from another's, he states as a basic criterion of rational discourse that the participants "must acknowledge a true and decisive standard to exist somewhere". He does not, as far as I can tell, demonstrate the existence of such a thing in matters of taste, although he hints at a sort of circular "learned men generally agree, therefore there must be a standard to which they are commonly referring" assumption.
2. Even more intriguing, and perhaps telling, is that in making this semi-circular argument he touches on the very difference between art and science that tarden began this conversation with. Reversing our usual formulation, he claims that since scientific work falls out of favor quickly, while artistic work endures, aesthetic judgments must not be so elusive after all. But this seems fairly idiotic to me. Scientific matters do not "fall out of favor", they are refuted. An argument about whether the earth's orbit is circular is very different than an argument about whether the ending of Romeo & Juliet is a cop-out. Individual scientific works spend short lives as the state of the art, but as syllogisms they are immortal. "If x then y" remains valid even after we've discovered that not x. Nothing of this certainty can be said about art. The long lives of old artworks, in fact, seems like one of the most glaring indications that art isn't much amenable to reason.
― glenn mcdonald, Friday, 15 June 2001 00:00 (twenty-three years ago) link